Product Code Database
Example Keywords: raincoat -glove $70
barcode-scavenger
   » » Wiki: Social Choice Theory
Tag Wiki 'Social Choice Theory'.
Tag

Social choice theory is a branch of welfare economics that extends the to collective decision-making.

(1983). 9780521122559, Cambridge University Press. .
Social choice studies the behavior of different mathematical procedures (social welfare functions) used to combine individual preferences into a coherent whole.For example, in Kenneth J. Arrow (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley, ch. II, section 2, A Notation for Preferences and Choice, and ch. III, "The Social Welfare Function". (2008). "Social Choice". The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, Abstract & TOC. It contrasts with political science in that it is a normative field that studies how a society can make good decisions, whereas political science is a descriptive field that observes how societies actually do make decisions. While social choice began as a branch of economics and decision theory, it has since received substantial contributions from , , political science, and .

Real-world examples of social choice rules include and parliamentary procedures for voting on laws, as well as ; as such, the field is occasionally called voting theory.

(1992). 9780521360524, Cambridge University Press. .
It is closely related to , which uses to model social choice with imperfect information and citizens.

Social choice differs from in that the latter is concerned with how individuals, rather than societies, can make rational decisions.


History
The earliest work on social choice theory comes from the writings of the Marquis de Condorcet, who formulated several key results including his jury theorem and his example showing the impossibility of . His work was prefigured by 's 1299 manuscript Ars Electionis ( The Art of Elections), which discussed many of the same concepts, but was lost in the Late Middle Ages and only rediscovered in the early 21st century.

's book Social Choice and Individual Values is often recognized as inaugurating the modern era of social choice theory. Later work has also considered approaches to legal compensation, , variable populations, partial of social-choice ,Walter Bossert and John A. Weymark (2008). "Social Choice (New Developments)," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, Abstract & TOC. natural resources, capabilities and functionings approaches,

(2025). 9780444508942
and measures of .
(2025). 9780444829146
Amartya Sen (1987 2008). "Justice," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract & TOC.
  Bertil Tungodden (2008). "Justice (New Perspectives)," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract.
  Louis Kaplow (2008). "Pareto Principle and Competing Principles," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract.
  Amartya K. Sen (1979 1984). Collective Choice and Social Welfare, New York: Elsevier, (description):
    ch. 9, "Equity and Justice," pp. 131-51.
    ch. 9*, "Impersonality and Collective Quasi-Orderings," pp. 152-160.
  Kenneth J. Arrow (1983). Collected Papers, v. 1, Social Choice and Justice, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, Description, contents, and chapter-preview links.
  Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert, and David Donaldson, 2002. "Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice", in Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, edited by Kenneth J. Arrow, Amartya K. Sen, and Kotaro Suzumura, v. 1, ch. 11, pp. 543–596. Abstract.
(2025). 9780444829146


Key results

Arrow's impossibility theorem
Arrow's impossibility theorem is a key result showing that social choice functions based only on , rather than , will behave (unless they are dictatorial). Such systems violate independence of irrelevant alternatives, meaning they suffer from —the system can behave erratically in response to changes in the quality or popularity of one of the options.


Condorcet cycles
Condorcet's example demonstrates that cannot be thought of as being the same as simple or majoritarianism; otherwise, it will be when three or more options are available. Majority rule can create cycles that violate the transitive property: Attempting to use majority rule as a social choice function creates situations where we have A better than B and B better than C, but C is also better than A.

This contrasts with May's theorem, which shows that simple majority is the optimal voting mechanism when there are only two outcomes, and only ordinal preferences are allowed.


Harsanyi's theorem
's utilitarian theorem shows that if individuals have preferences that are well-behaved under uncertainty (i.e. coherent), the only coherent and Pareto efficient social choice function is the . This lends some support to the viewpoint expressed of John Stuart Mill, who identified democracy with the ideal of maximizing the (or ) of society as a whole, under an equal consideration of interests.


Manipulation theorems
Gibbard's theorem provides limitations on the ability of any voting rule to elicit honest preferences from voters, showing that no voting rule is strategyproof (i.e. does not depend on other voters' preferences) for elections with 3 or more outcomes.

The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem proves a stronger result for , showing that no such voting rule can be sincere (i.e. free of reversed preferences).


Median voter theorem

Mechanism design
The field of , a subset of social choice theory, deals with the identification of rules that preserve while incentivizing agents to honestly reveal their preferences. One particularly important result is the revelation principle, which is almost a reversal of Gibbard's theorem: for any given social choice function, there exists a mechanism that obtains the same results but incentivizes participants to be completely honest.

Because mechanism design places stronger assumptions on the behavior of participants, it is sometimes possible to design mechanisms for social choice that accomplish apparently-"impossible" tasks. For example, by allowing agents to compensate each other for losses with transfers, the Vickrey–Clarke–Groves (VCG) mechanism can achieve the "impossible" according to Gibbard's theorem: the mechanism ensures honest behavior from participants, while still achieving a Pareto efficient outcome. As a result, the VCG mechanism can be considered a "better" way to make decisions than voting (though only so long as monetary transfers are possible).


Others
If the domain of preferences is restricted to those that include a majority-strength Condorcet winner, then selecting that winner is the unique resolvable, neutral, anonymous, and non-manipulable voting rule.


Interpersonal utility comparison
Social choice theory is the study of theoretical and practical methods to aggregate or combine individual preferences into a collective social welfare function. The field generally assumes that individuals have , and it follows that they can be modeled using , by the VNM theorem. But much of the research in the field assumes that those utility functions are internal to humans, lack a meaningful unit of measure and cannot be compared across different individuals.Lionel Robbins (1932, 1935, 2nd ed.). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, London: Macmillan. Links for 1932 HTML and 1935 facsimile. Whether this type of interpersonal utility comparison is possible or not significantly alters the available mathematical structures for social welfare functions and social choice theory.

In one perspective, following , have argued that preferences and utility functions of individuals are interpersonally comparable and may therefore be added together to arrive at a measure of aggregate utility. Utilitarian ethics call for maximizing this aggregate.

In contrast many twentieth century economists, following , questioned whether such measures of utility could be measured, or even considered meaningful. Following arguments similar to those espoused by , Robbins argued concepts of were unscientific and . Consider for instance the law of diminishing marginal utility, according to which utility of an added quantity of a good decreases with the amount of the good that is already in possession of the individual. It has been used to defend transfers of wealth from the "rich" to the "poor" on the premise that the former do not derive as much utility as the latter from an extra unit of income. Robbins argued that this notion is beyond ; that is, one cannot measure changes in the utility of someone else, nor is it required by positive theory.Lionel Robbins (1932, 1935, 2nd ed.). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, London: Macmillan. Links for 1932 HTML and 1935 facsimile.

Apologists for the interpersonal comparison of utility have argued that Robbins claimed too much. agreed that perfect comparisons of mental states are not practically possible, but people can still make some comparisons thanks to their similar backgrounds, cultural experiences, and psychologies. argues that even if interpersonal comparisons of utility are imperfect, we can still say that (despite being positive for ) the Great Fire of Rome had a negative overall value. Harsanyi and Sen thus argue that at least partial comparability of utility is possible, and social choice theory should proceed under that assumption.


Relationship to public choice theory
Despite the similar names, "public choice" and "social choice" are two distinct fields that are only weakly related. Public choice deals with the modeling of as they actually exist in the real world, and is primarily limited to positive economics (predicting how politicians and other stakeholders will act). It is therefore often thought of as the application of models to political science, in order to predict the behavior of . By contrast, social choice has a much more normative bent, and deals with the abstract study of decision procedures and their properties.

The Journal of Economic Literature classification codes place Social Choice under at (with Clubs, Committees, and Associations) whereas Public Choice falls under JEL D72 (Economic Models of Political Processes: , Elections, Legislatures, and Voting Behavior).


Empirical research
Since Arrow, social choice theory has been characterized by being predominantly and , but some research has aimed at estimating the frequency of various voting paradoxes, such as the Condorcet paradox. A summary of 37 individual studies, covering a total of 265 real-world elections, large and small, found 25 instances of a Condorcet paradox for a total likelihood of 9.4%. While examples of the paradox seem to occur often in small settings like parliaments, very few examples have been found in larger groups (electorates), although some have been identified. However, the frequency of such paradoxes depends heavily on the number of options and other factors.


Rules
Let X be a set of possible 'states of the world' or 'alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from X. For example, in a single-winner election, X may represent the set of candidates; in a resource allocation setting, X may represent all possible allocations.

Let I be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each i \in I, let u_i:X\longrightarrow\mathbb{R} be a , describing the amount of happiness an individual i derives from each possible state.

A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data (u_i)_{i \in I} to select some element(s) from X which are 'best' for society. The question of what 'best' means is a common question in social choice theory. The following rules are most common:

  • Utilitarian rule – sometimes called the max-sum rule or – aims to maximize the sum of utilities.
  • Egalitarian rule – sometimes called the max-min rule or – aims to maximize the smallest utility.


Social choice functions
A social choice function, sometimes called a in the context of politics, is a rule that takes an individual's complete and transitive preferences over a set of outcomes and returns a single chosen outcome (or a set of tied outcomes). We can think of this subset as the winners of an election, and compare different social choice functions based on which axioms or mathematical properties they fulfill.

Arrow's impossibility theorem is what often comes to mind when one thinks about impossibility theorems in voting. There are several famous theorems concerning social choice functions. The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem implies that the only rule satisfying non-imposition (every alternative can be chosen) and strategyproofness when there are more than two candidates is the dictatorship mechanism. That is, a voter may be able to cast a ballot that misrepresents their preferences to obtain a result that is more favorable to them under their sincere preferences. May's theorem shows that when there are only two candidates and , the simple majority vote is the unique neutral, anonymous, and positively-responsive voting rule.


See also


Notes
  • (1951, 2nd ed., 1963). Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley.
  • _____, (1972). "General Economic Equilibrium: Purpose, Analytic Techniques, Collective Choice", Nobel Prize Lecture, Link to text, with Section 8 on the theory and background.
  • _____, (1983). Collected Papers, v. 1, Social Choice and Justice, Oxford: Blackwell
  • Arrow, Kenneth J., Amartya K. Sen, and Kotaro Suzumura, eds. (1997). Social Choice Re-Examined, 2 vol., London: Palgrave Macmillan &
  • _____, eds. (2002). Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, v. 1. Chapter-preview links.
  • _____, ed. (2011). Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, v. 2, Amsterdam: Elsevier. Chapter-preview links.
  • Bossert, Walter and John A. Weymark (2008). "Social Choice (New Developments)," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, London: Palgrave Macmillan Abstract.
  • Dryzek, John S. and Christian List (2003). "Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation," British Journal of Political Science Https://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/4092266?uid=3739936&uid=2&uid=4&uid=3739256&sid=21102056001967, 2002 PDF link.
  • Feldman, Allan M. and Roberto Serrano (2006). Welfare Economics and Social Choice Theory, 2nd ed., New York: Springer , Arrow-searchable chapter previews.
  • (1996). Théories économiques de la justice, Paris: Economica.
  • (2025). 9780199297511, Oxford University Press.
  • (1987). "Interpersonal Utility Comparisons," The , v. 2, London: Palgrave, pp. 955–58.
  • (1988). 9780521424585, Cambridge University Press.
  • (2025). 9780521722131, Cambridge University Press.
  • (1935). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, 2nd ed., London: Macmillan, ch. VI
  • ____, (1938). "Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment," Economic Journal, 43(4), 635–41.
  • (1970 1984). Collective Choice and Social Welfare, New York: Elsevier Description.
  • _____, (1998). "The Possibility of Social Choice", Nobel Prize Lecture [24].
  • _____, (1987). "Social Choice," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 4, London: Palgrave, pp. 382–93.
  • _____, (2008). "Social Choice,". The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, London: Palgrave Abstract.
  • (2025). 9780521899437, Cambridge University Press. .
    . A comprehensive reference from a computational perspective; see Chapter 9. Downloadable free online.
  • (1983). Rational Choice, Collective Decisions, and Social Welfare, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • (2025). 9780521008839, Cambridge University Press. .


External links

Page 1 of 1
1
Page 1 of 1
1

Account

Social:
Pages:  ..   .. 
Items:  .. 

Navigation

General: Atom Feed Atom Feed  .. 
Help:  ..   .. 
Category:  ..   .. 
Media:  ..   .. 
Posts:  ..   ..   .. 

Statistics

Page:  .. 
Summary:  .. 
1 Tags
10/10 Page Rank
5 Page Refs
3s Time